Citations
2461 | The principles of psychology
- James
- 1950
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...ought comprehend it, so as to utter a word about it? If no one asks me, I know: if I wish to explain it to one who asketh, I know not. Saint Augustine, Confessions, Book 11 How long will it take you to read this chapter? The objective time, as measured by the clock, might depend on whether you’re scrutinizing every detail, or just skimming to get the main ideas. The subjective time might vary according to physiological factors like your pulse and body temperature (Cohen, 1967; Ornstein, 1969), psychological factors like how much the text engages your interest and attention (Glicksohn, 2001; 3 James, 1890; Zakay & Block, 1997), and some surprising environmental factors like the size of the room you’re sitting in (DeLong, 1981). Although subjective duration is among the earliest topics investigated by experimental psychologists (Mach, 1886), the cognitive sciences have yet to produce a comprehensive theory of how people track the passage of time, or even to agree on a set of principles that consistently govern people’s duration estimates. A excerpt from a review by Zakay and Block (1997) illustrates the current state of confusion: People may estimate filled durations as being longer than empty ... |
1293 |
Speaking: From intention to articulation
- Levelt
- 1989
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...ng that were consistent with linguistic metaphors only because they were required to process space or time in language. Would the same relations between representations of space and time be found if participants were tested on nonlinguistic tasks? The fact that people communicate via language replete with anaphora, ambiguity, metonymy, sarcasm, and deixis seems proof that what we say provides only a thumbnail sketch of what we think. Most theorists posit at least some independence between semantic representations and underlying conceptual representations (Jackendoff, 1972; Katz & Fodor, 1963; Levelt, 1989; cf., Fodor, 1975). Even those who posit a single, shared ‘level’ of representation for linguistic meaning and nonlinguistic concepts allow that semantic structures must constitute only a subset of conceptual structures (Chomsky, 1975; Jackendoff, 1983). Because we may think differently when we’re using language and when we’re not, well-founded doubts persist about how deeply patterns in language truly reflect – and shape – our nonlinguistic thought. According to linguist Dan Slobin (1996): Any utterance is a selective schematization of a concept – a schematization that is in some ways depend... |
1050 | Philosophy in the flesh: the embodied mind and its challenge to western thought - Lakoff, Johnson - 1999 |
1004 |
How the mind works
- Pinker
- 1997
(Show Context)
Citation Context ... compose symphonies, invent calculus, or imagine time travel? How did foragers become physicists in an eyeblink of evolutionary time? The human capacity for abstract thought seems to far exceed what could have benefited our predecessors, yet natural selection can only effect changes that are immediately useful. The apparent evolutionary uselessness of human intelligence drove Alfred Wallace, Darwin’s co-founder of the theory of evolution by natural selection, to abandon their theory and invoke creationism to explain our capacity for abstract thought (Darwin, 1859/1998, 1874/1998; Gould, 1980; Pinker, 1997; Wallace, 1870/2003).2 Darwin’s own formulation of evolutionary theory points toward an elegant potential solution to Wallace’s dilemma: sometimes organisms recycle old structures for new uses. An organ built via selection for a specific role may be fortuitously suited to perform other unselected roles, as well. For example, the fossil record suggests that feathers were not originally ‘designed’ for flying. Rather, they evolved to regulate body temperature in small running dinosaurs, and were only later co-opted for flight (Gould, 1991). The process of adapting existing structures for new fun... |
875 |
Semantic interpretation in generative grammar
- Jackendoff
- 1972
(Show Context)
Citation Context ... not be sensible to say that “the cat sat on the price / debate / issue / limit / appearance.” This test is similar to a test of sensible predicates for concrete vs. abstract entities devised by Fred Sommer (1963; cf., Turner, 2005). Based on examples like these, linguists have argued that people create abstract domains by importing structure from concepts grounded in physical experience. Although anticipated by others (e.g., Lafargue, 1898/1906), this idea appears to have been first articulated as the Thematic Relations Hypothesis (TRH) in 1965, by Jeffery Gruber. TRH was later elaborated by Jackendoff (1972; 1983) who wrote: The psychological claim behind [Gruber’s linguistic discovery] is that the mind does not manufacture abstract concepts out of thin air…it adapts machinery that is already there, both in the development of the individual organism and in the evolutionary development of the species. (1983, pg. 188-9) Not all theorists agree on the significance of metaphorical language for theories of mental representation. Gregory Murphy (1996; 1997) raised concerns about both the vagueness of the psychological processes suggested by linguists and about the limitations of purely linguistic evid... |
828 | An Essay Concerning Human Understanding
- Locke
- 1690
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...rations and displacements were fully crossed, so there was no correlation between the spatial and temporal components of the stimuli. As such, one stimulus dimension served as a distractor for the other: an irrelevant piece of information that could potentially interfere with task performance. Patterns of crossdimensional interference were analyzed to reveal relationships between spatial and temporal representations.3 Broadly speaking, there are three possible relationships between people’s mental representations of space and time. First, the two domains could be symmetrically dependent. John Locke (1689/1995) argued that space and time are mutually inextricable in our minds, concluding that, “expansion and duration do mutually embrace and comprehend each other; every part of space being in every part of duration, and every part of duration in every part of expansion” (p. 140). Alternatively, our ideas of space and time could be independent. Any apparent relatedness could be due to structural similarities between essentially unrelated domains (Murphy, 1996, 1997). A third possibility is that time and space could be asymmetrically dependent. Representations in one domain could be parasitic on ... |
791 |
Semantics and Cognition
- Jackendoff
- 1983
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...) What makes time perception so difficult to understand? Ornstein (1969) argues that although we experience the passage of time, the idea that time can be perceived through the senses is misleading (cf. Evans, 2004): One major reason for the continuing scattering of [researchers’] effort has been that time is treated as if it were a sensory process. If time were a sensory process like vision…we would have an ‘organ’ of time experience such as the eye. (pg. 34) Although time is not something we can see or touch, we often talk about it as if it were (Boroditsky, 2000; Clark, 1973; Gruber, 1965; Jackendoff, 1983; Lakoff & Johnson, 1980). Consider the following pair of sentences: i. They moved the truck forward two meters. ii. They moved the meeting forward two hours. The truck in sentence i. is a physical object which can move forward through space, and whose motion we might see, hear, or feel, from the staring point to the ending point. By contrast, there is no literal motion described in sentence ii. The meeting is not translated through space, and there is no way to experience its ‘movement’ through time via the senses. Events that occur in time are more abstract than objects that exist in space i... |
550 | Learnability and cognition: The acquisition of argument structure - Pinker - 1989 |
435 |
Foundations of Cognitive Grammar
- Langacker
- 1986
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...eferences to the physical world were bleached out. The circuits could serve as a scaffolding whose slots are filled with symbols for more abstract concerns like states, possessions, ideas, and desires. (pg. 355) As evidence that abstract domains arose from circuits designed for reasoning about the physical world, Pinker appeals to patterns observed in language. Many linguists have noted that when people talk about states, possessions, ideas, and desires, they do so by co-opting the language of intuitive physics (Clark, 1973, Gibbs, 1994; Gruber, 1965; Jackendoff, 1983; Lakoff & Johnson, 1980; Langacker, 1987; Talmy, 1988). In particular, words borrowed from physical domains of space, force, and motion, give rise to metaphors for countless abstract ideas. 1l a high shelf 1m a high price 2l a big building 2m a big debate 3l forcing the door 3m forcing the issue 4l pushing the button 4m pushing the limit 5l keeping the roof up 5m keeping appearances up 5 For each pair above, sentence l illustrates a literal use and sentence m a metaphorical use of the italicized words. The concrete objects described in the literal sentences (e.g., shelf, building, door, button, roof) belong to a different ontologica... |
311 |
The structure of a semantic theory
- Katz, Fodor
- 1963
(Show Context)
Citation Context ... and temporal thinking that were consistent with linguistic metaphors only because they were required to process space or time in language. Would the same relations between representations of space and time be found if participants were tested on nonlinguistic tasks? The fact that people communicate via language replete with anaphora, ambiguity, metonymy, sarcasm, and deixis seems proof that what we say provides only a thumbnail sketch of what we think. Most theorists posit at least some independence between semantic representations and underlying conceptual representations (Jackendoff, 1972; Katz & Fodor, 1963; Levelt, 1989; cf., Fodor, 1975). Even those who posit a single, shared ‘level’ of representation for linguistic meaning and nonlinguistic concepts allow that semantic structures must constitute only a subset of conceptual structures (Chomsky, 1975; Jackendoff, 1983). Because we may think differently when we’re using language and when we’re not, well-founded doubts persist about how deeply patterns in language truly reflect – and shape – our nonlinguistic thought. According to linguist Dan Slobin (1996): Any utterance is a selective schematization of a concept – a schematization that is in so... |
260 |
The poetics of mind: Figurative thought, language, and understanding
- Gibbs
- 1994
(Show Context)
Citation Context ..., the copies’ connections to the eyes and muscles were severed, and references to the physical world were bleached out. The circuits could serve as a scaffolding whose slots are filled with symbols for more abstract concerns like states, possessions, ideas, and desires. (pg. 355) As evidence that abstract domains arose from circuits designed for reasoning about the physical world, Pinker appeals to patterns observed in language. Many linguists have noted that when people talk about states, possessions, ideas, and desires, they do so by co-opting the language of intuitive physics (Clark, 1973, Gibbs, 1994; Gruber, 1965; Jackendoff, 1983; Lakoff & Johnson, 1980; Langacker, 1987; Talmy, 1988). In particular, words borrowed from physical domains of space, force, and motion, give rise to metaphors for countless abstract ideas. 1l a high shelf 1m a high price 2l a big building 2m a big debate 3l forcing the door 3m forcing the issue 4l pushing the button 4m pushing the limit 5l keeping the roof up 5m keeping appearances up 5 For each pair above, sentence l illustrates a literal use and sentence m a metaphorical use of the italicized words. The concrete objects described in the literal sentences (e.... |
247 | Force dynamics in language and cognition
- Talmy
- 1988
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...physical world were bleached out. The circuits could serve as a scaffolding whose slots are filled with symbols for more abstract concerns like states, possessions, ideas, and desires. (pg. 355) As evidence that abstract domains arose from circuits designed for reasoning about the physical world, Pinker appeals to patterns observed in language. Many linguists have noted that when people talk about states, possessions, ideas, and desires, they do so by co-opting the language of intuitive physics (Clark, 1973, Gibbs, 1994; Gruber, 1965; Jackendoff, 1983; Lakoff & Johnson, 1980; Langacker, 1987; Talmy, 1988). In particular, words borrowed from physical domains of space, force, and motion, give rise to metaphors for countless abstract ideas. 1l a high shelf 1m a high price 2l a big building 2m a big debate 3l forcing the door 3m forcing the issue 4l pushing the button 4m pushing the limit 5l keeping the roof up 5m keeping appearances up 5 For each pair above, sentence l illustrates a literal use and sentence m a metaphorical use of the italicized words. The concrete objects described in the literal sentences (e.g., shelf, building, door, button, roof) belong to a different ontological category tha... |
200 | Exaptation — a missing term in the science of form. - Gould, Vrba - 1982 |
199 |
From “thought and language” to “thinking for speaking
- Slobin
- 1996
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...semantic representations and underlying conceptual representations (Jackendoff, 1972; Katz & Fodor, 1963; Levelt, 1989; cf., Fodor, 1975). Even those who posit a single, shared ‘level’ of representation for linguistic meaning and nonlinguistic concepts allow that semantic structures must constitute only a subset of conceptual structures (Chomsky, 1975; Jackendoff, 1983). Because we may think differently when we’re using language and when we’re not, well-founded doubts persist about how deeply patterns in language truly reflect – and shape – our nonlinguistic thought. According to linguist Dan Slobin (1996): Any utterance is a selective schematization of a concept – a schematization that is in some ways dependent on the grammaticized meanings of the 7 speaker’s particular language, recruited for the purposes of verbal expression. (pg. 75-76) Slobin argues that when people are “thinking for speaking” (and presumably for reading or listening to speech), their thoughts are structured, in part, according to their language and its peculiarities. Consequently, speakers of different languages may think differently when they are using language. But how about when people are not thinking for speaking? Ev... |
124 |
Metaphors we live by. Chicago:
- Lakoff, Johnson
- 1980
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...perception so difficult to understand? Ornstein (1969) argues that although we experience the passage of time, the idea that time can be perceived through the senses is misleading (cf. Evans, 2004): One major reason for the continuing scattering of [researchers’] effort has been that time is treated as if it were a sensory process. If time were a sensory process like vision…we would have an ‘organ’ of time experience such as the eye. (pg. 34) Although time is not something we can see or touch, we often talk about it as if it were (Boroditsky, 2000; Clark, 1973; Gruber, 1965; Jackendoff, 1983; Lakoff & Johnson, 1980). Consider the following pair of sentences: i. They moved the truck forward two meters. ii. They moved the meeting forward two hours. The truck in sentence i. is a physical object which can move forward through space, and whose motion we might see, hear, or feel, from the staring point to the ending point. By contrast, there is no literal motion described in sentence ii. The meeting is not translated through space, and there is no way to experience its ‘movement’ through time via the senses. Events that occur in time are more abstract than objects that exist in space insomuch as we typically h... |
96 | Spatial representations activated during real-time comprehension of verbs
- Richardson, Spivey, et al.
- 2003
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...xperiments unequivocally support the hypothesis that people incorporate spatial information into their time judgments more than they incorporate temporal information into their spatial judgments. These findings converge with those of Cantor & Thomas (1977), who showed that spatial information influences temporal judgments but not vice versa for very briefly presented stimuli (30-70 msecs). Previous behavioral tests of Conceptual Metaphor Theory have used linguistic stimuli (Boroditsky, 2000, 2001; Boroditsky & Ramscar, 2002; Gibbs, 1994; Meier & Robinson, 2004; Meier, Robinson, & Clore, 2004; Richardson, Spivey, Barsalou, & McRae, 2003; Schubert, 2005; Torralbo, Santiago, & Lupiáñez, 2006). While these studies support the psychological reality of Conceptual Metaphor, they leave open the possibility that people only think about abstract domains like time metaphorically when they are using language (i.e., when they are thinking for speaking (E. Clark, 2003; Slobin, 1996)). Experiments described above used nonlinguistic stimuli and responses, and demonstrated that even our low-level perceptuo-motor representations in the domains of space and time are related as predicted by linguistic metaphors. Over the past century of psycho... |
73 |
Your highness: vertical positions as perceptual symbols of power.
- Schubert
- 2005
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...is that people incorporate spatial information into their time judgments more than they incorporate temporal information into their spatial judgments. These findings converge with those of Cantor & Thomas (1977), who showed that spatial information influences temporal judgments but not vice versa for very briefly presented stimuli (30-70 msecs). Previous behavioral tests of Conceptual Metaphor Theory have used linguistic stimuli (Boroditsky, 2000, 2001; Boroditsky & Ramscar, 2002; Gibbs, 1994; Meier & Robinson, 2004; Meier, Robinson, & Clore, 2004; Richardson, Spivey, Barsalou, & McRae, 2003; Schubert, 2005; Torralbo, Santiago, & Lupiáñez, 2006). While these studies support the psychological reality of Conceptual Metaphor, they leave open the possibility that people only think about abstract domains like time metaphorically when they are using language (i.e., when they are thinking for speaking (E. Clark, 2003; Slobin, 1996)). Experiments described above used nonlinguistic stimuli and responses, and demonstrated that even our low-level perceptuo-motor representations in the domains of space and time are related as predicted by linguistic metaphors. Over the past century of psychophysical experim... |
71 | Temporal cognition.
- Zakay, Block
- 1997
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...; Ornstein, 1969), psychological factors like how much the text engages your interest and attention (Glicksohn, 2001; 3 James, 1890; Zakay & Block, 1997), and some surprising environmental factors like the size of the room you’re sitting in (DeLong, 1981). Although subjective duration is among the earliest topics investigated by experimental psychologists (Mach, 1886), the cognitive sciences have yet to produce a comprehensive theory of how people track the passage of time, or even to agree on a set of principles that consistently govern people’s duration estimates. A excerpt from a review by Zakay and Block (1997) illustrates the current state of confusion: People may estimate filled durations as being longer than empty durations, but sometimes the reverse is found. Duration judgments tend to be shorter if a more difficult task is performed than if an easier task is performed, but again the opposite has also been reported. People usually make longer duration estimates for complex than for simple stimuli, although some researchers have found the opposite. (pg. 12) What makes time perception so difficult to understand? Ornstein (1969) argues that although we experience the passage of time, the idea that ... |
69 |
On the Experience of Time,
- Ornstein
- 1969
(Show Context)
Citation Context ... action. 1.1 Time as an abstract domain For what is time? Who can readily and briefly explain this? Who can even in thought comprehend it, so as to utter a word about it? If no one asks me, I know: if I wish to explain it to one who asketh, I know not. Saint Augustine, Confessions, Book 11 How long will it take you to read this chapter? The objective time, as measured by the clock, might depend on whether you’re scrutinizing every detail, or just skimming to get the main ideas. The subjective time might vary according to physiological factors like your pulse and body temperature (Cohen, 1967; Ornstein, 1969), psychological factors like how much the text engages your interest and attention (Glicksohn, 2001; 3 James, 1890; Zakay & Block, 1997), and some surprising environmental factors like the size of the room you’re sitting in (DeLong, 1981). Although subjective duration is among the earliest topics investigated by experimental psychologists (Mach, 1886), the cognitive sciences have yet to produce a comprehensive theory of how people track the passage of time, or even to agree on a set of principles that consistently govern people’s duration estimates. A excerpt from a review by Zakay and Block (... |
68 |
Studies in lexical relations.
- Gruber
- 1965
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...osite. (pg. 12) What makes time perception so difficult to understand? Ornstein (1969) argues that although we experience the passage of time, the idea that time can be perceived through the senses is misleading (cf. Evans, 2004): One major reason for the continuing scattering of [researchers’] effort has been that time is treated as if it were a sensory process. If time were a sensory process like vision…we would have an ‘organ’ of time experience such as the eye. (pg. 34) Although time is not something we can see or touch, we often talk about it as if it were (Boroditsky, 2000; Clark, 1973; Gruber, 1965; Jackendoff, 1983; Lakoff & Johnson, 1980). Consider the following pair of sentences: i. They moved the truck forward two meters. ii. They moved the meeting forward two hours. The truck in sentence i. is a physical object which can move forward through space, and whose motion we might see, hear, or feel, from the staring point to the ending point. By contrast, there is no literal motion described in sentence ii. The meeting is not translated through space, and there is no way to experience its ‘movement’ through time via the senses. Events that occur in time are more abstract than objects tha... |
64 | On metaphoric representation.
- Murphy
- 1996
(Show Context)
Citation Context ..., this idea appears to have been first articulated as the Thematic Relations Hypothesis (TRH) in 1965, by Jeffery Gruber. TRH was later elaborated by Jackendoff (1972; 1983) who wrote: The psychological claim behind [Gruber’s linguistic discovery] is that the mind does not manufacture abstract concepts out of thin air…it adapts machinery that is already there, both in the development of the individual organism and in the evolutionary development of the species. (1983, pg. 188-9) Not all theorists agree on the significance of metaphorical language for theories of mental representation. Gregory Murphy (1996; 1997) raised concerns about both the vagueness of the psychological processes suggested by linguists and about the limitations of purely linguistic evidence for metaphorical conceptual structure. Murphy (1996) proposed that linguistic metaphors may merely reveal structural similarities between mental domains: not causal relationships. He argued that in the absence of corroborating nonlinguistic evidence, his Structural Similarity proposal should be preferred on grounds of simplicity: his view posits that all concepts are represented independently, on their own terms, whereas the metaphoric a... |
63 |
Why the sunny side is up: Associations between affect and vertical position.
- Meier, Robinson
- 2004
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...otion. [INSERT FIGURE 1 ABOUT HERE] Results of all six experiments unequivocally support the hypothesis that people incorporate spatial information into their time judgments more than they incorporate temporal information into their spatial judgments. These findings converge with those of Cantor & Thomas (1977), who showed that spatial information influences temporal judgments but not vice versa for very briefly presented stimuli (30-70 msecs). Previous behavioral tests of Conceptual Metaphor Theory have used linguistic stimuli (Boroditsky, 2000, 2001; Boroditsky & Ramscar, 2002; Gibbs, 1994; Meier & Robinson, 2004; Meier, Robinson, & Clore, 2004; Richardson, Spivey, Barsalou, & McRae, 2003; Schubert, 2005; Torralbo, Santiago, & Lupiáñez, 2006). While these studies support the psychological reality of Conceptual Metaphor, they leave open the possibility that people only think about abstract domains like time metaphorically when they are using language (i.e., when they are thinking for speaking (E. Clark, 2003; Slobin, 1996)). Experiments described above used nonlinguistic stimuli and responses, and demonstrated that even our low-level perceptuo-motor representations in the domains of space and time are ... |
62 |
The Relation of Habitual Thought and Behavior to Language
- Whorf
- 1939
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...ed more recently by Pinker (1994) and by Lila Gleitman and colleagues (Papafragou, Massey, & Gleitman, 2002; Snedeker & Gleitman, 2004). The Shallow View proposed here can be considered a variety of the universalist view that can plausibly be maintained despite recent psycholinguistic evidence supporting the Whorfian hypothesis (e.g., Boroditsky, 2001). Skepticism about some Whorfian claims has been well founded (see Pinker, 1994, ch. 3, for a review of evidence against the Whorfian hypothesis). A notorious fallacy, attributable in part to Whorf, illustrates the need for methodological rigor. Whorf (1939/2000) argued that Eskimos must conceive of snow differently than English speakers because the Eskimo lexicon contains multiple words that distinguish different types of snow, whereas English has only one word to describe all types. The exact number of snow words the Eskimos were purported to have is not clear. This number has now been inflated by the popular press to as many as four-hundred. According to a Western Greenlandic Eskimo dictionary published in Whorf’s time, however, Eskimos may have had as few as two distinct words for snow (Pullum, 1991). Setting aside Whorf’s imprecision and th... |
53 | Shake, rattle, 'n' roll: The representation of motion in language and cognition
- Papafragou, Massey, et al.
- 2002
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...epts of ‘time,’ ‘space,’ and ‘matter’ given in substantially the same form by experience to all men, or are they in part conditioned by the structure of particular languages?” (1939/2000, pg. 138.) This Whorfian question remains the subject of renewed interest and debate. Does language shape thought? The answer yes would call for a reexamination of the ‘universalist’ assumption that has guided Cognitive Science for decades, according to which nonlinguistic concepts are formed independently of the words that name them, and are invariant across languages and cultures (Fodor, 1975; Pinker, 1994, Papafragou, Massey, & Gleitman, 2002). This position is often attributed to Chomsky (1975), but has been articulated more recently by Pinker (1994) and by Lila Gleitman and colleagues (Papafragou, Massey, & Gleitman, 2002; Snedeker & Gleitman, 2004). The Shallow View proposed here can be considered a variety of the universalist view that can plausibly be maintained despite recent psycholinguistic evidence supporting the Whorfian hypothesis (e.g., Boroditsky, 2001). Skepticism about some Whorfian claims has been well founded (see Pinker, 1994, ch. 3, for a review of evidence against the Whorfian hypothesis). A notorious fallacy, ... |
46 |
The structure of time: Language, meaning and temporal cognition.
- Evans
- 2004
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...mate filled durations as being longer than empty durations, but sometimes the reverse is found. Duration judgments tend to be shorter if a more difficult task is performed than if an easier task is performed, but again the opposite has also been reported. People usually make longer duration estimates for complex than for simple stimuli, although some researchers have found the opposite. (pg. 12) What makes time perception so difficult to understand? Ornstein (1969) argues that although we experience the passage of time, the idea that time can be perceived through the senses is misleading (cf. Evans, 2004): One major reason for the continuing scattering of [researchers’] effort has been that time is treated as if it were a sensory process. If time were a sensory process like vision…we would have an ‘organ’ of time experience such as the eye. (pg. 34) Although time is not something we can see or touch, we often talk about it as if it were (Boroditsky, 2000; Clark, 1973; Gruber, 1965; Jackendoff, 1983; Lakoff & Johnson, 1980). Consider the following pair of sentences: i. They moved the truck forward two meters. ii. They moved the meeting forward two hours. The truck in sentence i. is a physical o... |
39 | Reasons to doubt the present evidence for metaphoric representation. - Murphy - 1997 |
37 | Temporal control and coordination: The multiple timer model.
- Ivry, Richardson
- 2002
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...ies if indeed Tau and Kappa effects reveal influences of imputed speed on time and space estimation, whereas the tasks described here test for interference between temporal and spatial information, per se. It is noteworthy that space influenced temporal judgments even for spatiotemporal stimuli that participants could experience directly. Growing lines are observable, and are arguably less abstract than entities like the ‘moving meeting’ described in section 1.1. Brief durations could, in principle, be mentally represented independently of space, by an interval-timer or pulse-accumulator (see Ivry & Richardson, 2002 for review), yet our data suggest that spatial representations are integral to the timing of even simple, observable events. Space may play an 12 indispensable role in forming more sophisticated and abstract temporal representations, such as very long intervals (e.g., the next millennium) and intervals that only exist in the past or the future (e.g., the 16th century), which we can never experience directly. Together, these experiments demonstrate that the metaphors we use can provide a window on the structure of our abstract concepts. They also raise a further question about relations betwee... |
31 |
Spatial metaphors in temporal reasoning. In
- Gentner
- 2001
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...nextricable in our minds, concluding that, “expansion and duration do mutually embrace and comprehend each other; every part of space being in every part of duration, and every part of duration in every part of expansion” (p. 140). Alternatively, our ideas of space and time could be independent. Any apparent relatedness could be due to structural similarities between essentially unrelated domains (Murphy, 1996, 1997). A third possibility is that time and space could be asymmetrically dependent. Representations in one domain could be parasitic on representations in the other (Boroditsky, 2000; Gentner, 2001; Gibbs, 1994; Lakoff & Johnson, 1980, 1999). These three possible relations between space and time predict three distinct patterns of cross-dimensional interference. If spatial and temporal representations are symmetrically dependent on one another, then any cross-dimensional interference should be approximately symmetric: line displacement should modulate estimates of line duration, and vice versa. Alternatively, if spatial and temporal representations are independent, there should be no significant cross-dimensional interference. However, if mental representations of time are asymmetrically... |
28 |
Flexible conceptual projection of time onto spatial frames of reference.
- Torralbo, Santiago, et al.
- 2006
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...ncorporate spatial information into their time judgments more than they incorporate temporal information into their spatial judgments. These findings converge with those of Cantor & Thomas (1977), who showed that spatial information influences temporal judgments but not vice versa for very briefly presented stimuli (30-70 msecs). Previous behavioral tests of Conceptual Metaphor Theory have used linguistic stimuli (Boroditsky, 2000, 2001; Boroditsky & Ramscar, 2002; Gibbs, 1994; Meier & Robinson, 2004; Meier, Robinson, & Clore, 2004; Richardson, Spivey, Barsalou, & McRae, 2003; Schubert, 2005; Torralbo, Santiago, & Lupiáñez, 2006). While these studies support the psychological reality of Conceptual Metaphor, they leave open the possibility that people only think about abstract domains like time metaphorically when they are using language (i.e., when they are thinking for speaking (E. Clark, 2003; Slobin, 1996)). Experiments described above used nonlinguistic stimuli and responses, and demonstrated that even our low-level perceptuo-motor representations in the domains of space and time are related as predicted by linguistic metaphors. Over the past century of psychophysical experimentation on space and time judgments, ... |
25 |
Why good guys wear white: Automatic inferences about stimulus valence based on color.
- Meier, Robinson, et al.
- 2004
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...ABOUT HERE] Results of all six experiments unequivocally support the hypothesis that people incorporate spatial information into their time judgments more than they incorporate temporal information into their spatial judgments. These findings converge with those of Cantor & Thomas (1977), who showed that spatial information influences temporal judgments but not vice versa for very briefly presented stimuli (30-70 msecs). Previous behavioral tests of Conceptual Metaphor Theory have used linguistic stimuli (Boroditsky, 2000, 2001; Boroditsky & Ramscar, 2002; Gibbs, 1994; Meier & Robinson, 2004; Meier, Robinson, & Clore, 2004; Richardson, Spivey, Barsalou, & McRae, 2003; Schubert, 2005; Torralbo, Santiago, & Lupiáñez, 2006). While these studies support the psychological reality of Conceptual Metaphor, they leave open the possibility that people only think about abstract domains like time metaphorically when they are using language (i.e., when they are thinking for speaking (E. Clark, 2003; Slobin, 1996)). Experiments described above used nonlinguistic stimuli and responses, and demonstrated that even our low-level perceptuo-motor representations in the domains of space and time are related as predicted by linguist... |
22 |
The tau effect - an example of psychological relativity.
- Helson
- 1930
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...taphorically when they are using language (i.e., when they are thinking for speaking (E. Clark, 2003; Slobin, 1996)). Experiments described above used nonlinguistic stimuli and responses, and demonstrated that even our low-level perceptuo-motor representations in the domains of space and time are related as predicted by linguistic metaphors. Over the past century of psychophysical experimentation on space and time judgments, two findings have emerged repeatedly: the Kappa effect and the Tau effect (Benussi, 1913; Bill & Teft, 1969; Cohen, 1967; Cohen, Hansel, & Sylvester, 1954; Collyer, 1977; Helson, 1930; Jones & Huang, 1982; Price-Williams, 1954; Sarrazin, Giraudo, Pailhous, & Bootsma, 2004). In a typical experiment, three light bulbs were arranged in a row and flashed in succession, forming two spatiotemporal intervals. Participants were asked to compare either the spatial or temporal extents of the two intervals. Often, time judgments were found to increase as a function of the spatial separation between stimuli (the Kappa effect), and distance judgments were found to increase as a function of the temporal separation between stimuli (the Tau effect). At first glance, these experiments appe... |
22 | Contributions to the analysis of sensations. - Mach - 1896 |
17 |
The philosophical significance of image schemas.
- Johnson
- 2005
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...olume metaphors in language, native English speakers’ performance on the Filling Tank task was statistically indistinguishable from the performance of the native Greek and Spanish speakers tested in Experiment 9. By encouraging the habitual use of either distance or volume metaphors, our natural linguistic environments may influence our everyday thinking about time in much the same way as this laboratory training task. These findings help to resolve apparent tensions between the proposal that perceptuo-motor image schemas underlie our abstract concepts and the notion of linguistic relativity. Johnson (2005) defines an image schema as “a dynamic recurring pattern of organism-environment interactions” (pg. 19). Presumably, people from all language communities inhabit the same physical world and interact with their environment using the same perceptuo-motor capacities, therefore the image schemas they develop should be universal. Yet, even if we all develop similar image schemas based on our physical experiences, Experiments 8-10 suggest the concepts that these image schemas undergird are not immutable. Duration can be understood both in terms of distance and in terms of volume. The extent to which... |
16 |
The great Eskimo vocabulary hoax.
- Pullum
- 1989
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...ustrates the need for methodological rigor. Whorf (1939/2000) argued that Eskimos must conceive of snow differently than English speakers because the Eskimo lexicon contains multiple words that distinguish different types of snow, whereas English has only one word to describe all types. The exact number of snow words the Eskimos were purported to have is not clear. This number has now been inflated by the popular press to as many as four-hundred. According to a Western Greenlandic Eskimo dictionary published in Whorf’s time, however, Eskimos may have had as few as two distinct words for snow (Pullum, 1991). Setting aside Whorf’s imprecision and the media’s exaggeration, there remains a critical missing link between Whorf’s data and his conclusions: Whorf (like many researchers today) used purely linguistic data to support inferences about nonlinguistic mental representations. Steven Pinker illustrates the resulting circularity of Whorf’s claim in this parody of his logic: 13 [They] speak differently so they must think differently. How do we know that they think differently? Just listen to the way they speak! (Pinker, 1994, pg. 61). Such circularity would be escaped if nonlinguistic evidence cou... |
15 |
Contributions to the Theory of Natural Selection
- Wallace
- 1871
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...onies, invent calculus, or imagine time travel? How did foragers become physicists in an eyeblink of evolutionary time? The human capacity for abstract thought seems to far exceed what could have benefited our predecessors, yet natural selection can only effect changes that are immediately useful. The apparent evolutionary uselessness of human intelligence drove Alfred Wallace, Darwin’s co-founder of the theory of evolution by natural selection, to abandon their theory and invoke creationism to explain our capacity for abstract thought (Darwin, 1859/1998, 1874/1998; Gould, 1980; Pinker, 1997; Wallace, 1870/2003).2 Darwin’s own formulation of evolutionary theory points toward an elegant potential solution to Wallace’s dilemma: sometimes organisms recycle old structures for new uses. An organ built via selection for a specific role may be fortuitously suited to perform other unselected roles, as well. For example, the fossil record suggests that feathers were not originally ‘designed’ for flying. Rather, they evolved to regulate body temperature in small running dinosaurs, and were only later co-opted for flight (Gould, 1991). The process of adapting existing structures for new functions, which D... |
12 | Dynamics of balancing space and time in memory: Tau and kappa effects revisited.
- Sarrazin, Giraudo, et al.
- 2004
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...y are thinking for speaking (E. Clark, 2003; Slobin, 1996)). Experiments described above used nonlinguistic stimuli and responses, and demonstrated that even our low-level perceptuo-motor representations in the domains of space and time are related as predicted by linguistic metaphors. Over the past century of psychophysical experimentation on space and time judgments, two findings have emerged repeatedly: the Kappa effect and the Tau effect (Benussi, 1913; Bill & Teft, 1969; Cohen, 1967; Cohen, Hansel, & Sylvester, 1954; Collyer, 1977; Helson, 1930; Jones & Huang, 1982; Price-Williams, 1954; Sarrazin, Giraudo, Pailhous, & Bootsma, 2004). In a typical experiment, three light bulbs were arranged in a row and flashed in succession, forming two spatiotemporal intervals. Participants were asked to compare either the spatial or temporal extents of the two intervals. Often, time judgments were found to increase as a function of the spatial separation between stimuli (the Kappa effect), and distance judgments were found to increase as a function of the temporal separation between stimuli (the Tau effect). At first glance, these experiments appear similar to those we report here; the Kappa effect seems consistent with our results, b... |
11 |
Temporal cognition and the phenomenology of time: A multiplicative function for apparent duration.
- Glicksohn
- 2001
(Show Context)
Citation Context ... Who can even in thought comprehend it, so as to utter a word about it? If no one asks me, I know: if I wish to explain it to one who asketh, I know not. Saint Augustine, Confessions, Book 11 How long will it take you to read this chapter? The objective time, as measured by the clock, might depend on whether you’re scrutinizing every detail, or just skimming to get the main ideas. The subjective time might vary according to physiological factors like your pulse and body temperature (Cohen, 1967; Ornstein, 1969), psychological factors like how much the text engages your interest and attention (Glicksohn, 2001; 3 James, 1890; Zakay & Block, 1997), and some surprising environmental factors like the size of the room you’re sitting in (DeLong, 1981). Although subjective duration is among the earliest topics investigated by experimental psychologists (Mach, 1886), the cognitive sciences have yet to produce a comprehensive theory of how people track the passage of time, or even to agree on a set of principles that consistently govern people’s duration estimates. A excerpt from a review by Zakay and Block (1997) illustrates the current state of confusion: People may estimate filled durations as being lon... |
9 |
Embodiment in language understanding: Sensory-motor representations for metaphoric reasoning about event descriptions.
- Narayanan
- 1997
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...s, but do they really think about them that way? 1.3 Evidence for Conceptual Metaphor The idea that conventionalized metaphors in language reveal the structure of abstract concepts is often associated with linguist George Lakoff and philosopher Mark Johnson, who described Conceptual Metaphor theory as one of “three major findings of cognitive science” (1999, pg. 3). Yet, this claim was supported almost entirely by linguistic evidence, supplemented by a computational model providing an in principle demonstration of how the meanings of some linguistic metaphors might be learned and represented (Narayanan, 1997). Despite the impressive body of linguistic theory and data that Lakoff & Johnson summarized, they offered little evidence that the importance of metaphor extends beyond language. Without nonlinguistic evidence for metaphorically structured mental representations, the idea that abstract thought is an exaptation from physical domains remained “just an avowal of faith” among scientists who believe that the mind must ultimately be explicable as a product of natural selection (Pinker, 1997, pg. 301). Boroditsky (2000) conducted some of the first behavioral tests of Conceptual Metaphor Theory. Her ... |
7 |
The kappa effect.
- Price-Williams
- 1954
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...nguage (i.e., when they are thinking for speaking (E. Clark, 2003; Slobin, 1996)). Experiments described above used nonlinguistic stimuli and responses, and demonstrated that even our low-level perceptuo-motor representations in the domains of space and time are related as predicted by linguistic metaphors. Over the past century of psychophysical experimentation on space and time judgments, two findings have emerged repeatedly: the Kappa effect and the Tau effect (Benussi, 1913; Bill & Teft, 1969; Cohen, 1967; Cohen, Hansel, & Sylvester, 1954; Collyer, 1977; Helson, 1930; Jones & Huang, 1982; Price-Williams, 1954; Sarrazin, Giraudo, Pailhous, & Bootsma, 2004). In a typical experiment, three light bulbs were arranged in a row and flashed in succession, forming two spatiotemporal intervals. Participants were asked to compare either the spatial or temporal extents of the two intervals. Often, time judgments were found to increase as a function of the spatial separation between stimuli (the Kappa effect), and distance judgments were found to increase as a function of the temporal separation between stimuli (the Tau effect). At first glance, these experiments appear similar to those we report here; the Kap... |
4 |
The language of thought. Cambridge:
- Fodor
- 1975
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...tent with linguistic metaphors only because they were required to process space or time in language. Would the same relations between representations of space and time be found if participants were tested on nonlinguistic tasks? The fact that people communicate via language replete with anaphora, ambiguity, metonymy, sarcasm, and deixis seems proof that what we say provides only a thumbnail sketch of what we think. Most theorists posit at least some independence between semantic representations and underlying conceptual representations (Jackendoff, 1972; Katz & Fodor, 1963; Levelt, 1989; cf., Fodor, 1975). Even those who posit a single, shared ‘level’ of representation for linguistic meaning and nonlinguistic concepts allow that semantic structures must constitute only a subset of conceptual structures (Chomsky, 1975; Jackendoff, 1983). Because we may think differently when we’re using language and when we’re not, well-founded doubts persist about how deeply patterns in language truly reflect – and shape – our nonlinguistic thought. According to linguist Dan Slobin (1996): Any utterance is a selective schematization of a concept – a schematization that is in some ways dependent on the grammati... |
3 |
Natural selection and the brain: Darwin vs. Wallace.
- Gould
- 1980
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...ur ability to compose symphonies, invent calculus, or imagine time travel? How did foragers become physicists in an eyeblink of evolutionary time? The human capacity for abstract thought seems to far exceed what could have benefited our predecessors, yet natural selection can only effect changes that are immediately useful. The apparent evolutionary uselessness of human intelligence drove Alfred Wallace, Darwin’s co-founder of the theory of evolution by natural selection, to abandon their theory and invoke creationism to explain our capacity for abstract thought (Darwin, 1859/1998, 1874/1998; Gould, 1980; Pinker, 1997; Wallace, 1870/2003).2 Darwin’s own formulation of evolutionary theory points toward an elegant potential solution to Wallace’s dilemma: sometimes organisms recycle old structures for new uses. An organ built via selection for a specific role may be fortuitously suited to perform other unselected roles, as well. For example, the fossil record suggests that feathers were not originally ‘designed’ for flying. Rather, they evolved to regulate body temperature in small running dinosaurs, and were only later co-opted for flight (Gould, 1991). The process of adapting existing structur... |
3 |
Ursprung der abstrakten ideen. Die Neue Zeit,
- Lafargue
- 1898
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...at physical relations they can sensibly be said to enter into. For example, it is sensible to say “the cat sat on the shelf / building / door / button / roof”, but it may not be sensible to say that “the cat sat on the price / debate / issue / limit / appearance.” This test is similar to a test of sensible predicates for concrete vs. abstract entities devised by Fred Sommer (1963; cf., Turner, 2005). Based on examples like these, linguists have argued that people create abstract domains by importing structure from concepts grounded in physical experience. Although anticipated by others (e.g., Lafargue, 1898/1906), this idea appears to have been first articulated as the Thematic Relations Hypothesis (TRH) in 1965, by Jeffery Gruber. TRH was later elaborated by Jackendoff (1972; 1983) who wrote: The psychological claim behind [Gruber’s linguistic discovery] is that the mind does not manufacture abstract concepts out of thin air…it adapts machinery that is already there, both in the development of the individual organism and in the evolutionary development of the species. (1983, pg. 188-9) Not all theorists agree on the significance of metaphorical language for theories of mental representation. Gr... |
3 |
Why is it hard to label our concepts? In Hall & Waxman (Eds.), Weaving a lexicon.
- Snedeker, Gleitman
- 2004
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...mains the subject of renewed interest and debate. Does language shape thought? The answer yes would call for a reexamination of the ‘universalist’ assumption that has guided Cognitive Science for decades, according to which nonlinguistic concepts are formed independently of the words that name them, and are invariant across languages and cultures (Fodor, 1975; Pinker, 1994, Papafragou, Massey, & Gleitman, 2002). This position is often attributed to Chomsky (1975), but has been articulated more recently by Pinker (1994) and by Lila Gleitman and colleagues (Papafragou, Massey, & Gleitman, 2002; Snedeker & Gleitman, 2004). The Shallow View proposed here can be considered a variety of the universalist view that can plausibly be maintained despite recent psycholinguistic evidence supporting the Whorfian hypothesis (e.g., Boroditsky, 2001). Skepticism about some Whorfian claims has been well founded (see Pinker, 1994, ch. 3, for a review of evidence against the Whorfian hypothesis). A notorious fallacy, attributable in part to Whorf, illustrates the need for methodological rigor. Whorf (1939/2000) argued that Eskimos must conceive of snow differently than English speakers because the Eskimo lexicon contains multi... |
2 |
Not necessarily a wing.
- Gould
- 1991
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...ract thought (Darwin, 1859/1998, 1874/1998; Gould, 1980; Pinker, 1997; Wallace, 1870/2003).2 Darwin’s own formulation of evolutionary theory points toward an elegant potential solution to Wallace’s dilemma: sometimes organisms recycle old structures for new uses. An organ built via selection for a specific role may be fortuitously suited to perform other unselected roles, as well. For example, the fossil record suggests that feathers were not originally ‘designed’ for flying. Rather, they evolved to regulate body temperature in small running dinosaurs, and were only later co-opted for flight (Gould, 1991). The process of adapting existing structures for new functions, which Darwin (1859/1993) gave the misleading name preadaptation, was later dubbed exaptation by evolutionary biologist Steven Jay Gould and paleontologist Elisabeth Vrba (1982). Gould argued that this process may explain the origin of many improbable biological and psychological structures. Can exaptation account for mental abilities in humans that could not have been selected for directly? If so, how might this have happened? Which adapted capacities might abstract domains be exapted from? Steven Pinker (1997) sketched the follo... |
2 |
Types of ontology.
- Sommer
- 1963
(Show Context)
Citation Context ... words. The concrete objects described in the literal sentences (e.g., shelf, building, door, button, roof) belong to a different ontological category than the abstract entities in the metaphorical examples, according a test of what physical relations they can sensibly be said to enter into. For example, it is sensible to say “the cat sat on the shelf / building / door / button / roof”, but it may not be sensible to say that “the cat sat on the price / debate / issue / limit / appearance.” This test is similar to a test of sensible predicates for concrete vs. abstract entities devised by Fred Sommer (1963; cf., Turner, 2005). Based on examples like these, linguists have argued that people create abstract domains by importing structure from concepts grounded in physical experience. Although anticipated by others (e.g., Lafargue, 1898/1906), this idea appears to have been first articulated as the Thematic Relations Hypothesis (TRH) in 1965, by Jeffery Gruber. TRH was later elaborated by Jackendoff (1972; 1983) who wrote: The psychological claim behind [Gruber’s linguistic discovery] is that the mind does not manufacture abstract concepts out of thin air…it adapts machinery that is already there,... |
2 |
The literal versus figurative dichotomy.
- Turner
- 2005
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...e objects described in the literal sentences (e.g., shelf, building, door, button, roof) belong to a different ontological category than the abstract entities in the metaphorical examples, according a test of what physical relations they can sensibly be said to enter into. For example, it is sensible to say “the cat sat on the shelf / building / door / button / roof”, but it may not be sensible to say that “the cat sat on the price / debate / issue / limit / appearance.” This test is similar to a test of sensible predicates for concrete vs. abstract entities devised by Fred Sommer (1963; cf., Turner, 2005). Based on examples like these, linguists have argued that people create abstract domains by importing structure from concepts grounded in physical experience. Although anticipated by others (e.g., Lafargue, 1898/1906), this idea appears to have been first articulated as the Thematic Relations Hypothesis (TRH) in 1965, by Jeffery Gruber. TRH was later elaborated by Jackendoff (1972; 1983) who wrote: The psychological claim behind [Gruber’s linguistic discovery] is that the mind does not manufacture abstract concepts out of thin air…it adapts machinery that is already there, both in the develop... |
1 | The descent of man. Amherst: Promethius Books. - Darwin - 1874 |
1 |
Space-time dependecies in psychophysical judgment of extent and duration: Algebraic models of the tau and kappa effects.
- Jones, Huang
- 1982
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...hen they are using language (i.e., when they are thinking for speaking (E. Clark, 2003; Slobin, 1996)). Experiments described above used nonlinguistic stimuli and responses, and demonstrated that even our low-level perceptuo-motor representations in the domains of space and time are related as predicted by linguistic metaphors. Over the past century of psychophysical experimentation on space and time judgments, two findings have emerged repeatedly: the Kappa effect and the Tau effect (Benussi, 1913; Bill & Teft, 1969; Cohen, 1967; Cohen, Hansel, & Sylvester, 1954; Collyer, 1977; Helson, 1930; Jones & Huang, 1982; Price-Williams, 1954; Sarrazin, Giraudo, Pailhous, & Bootsma, 2004). In a typical experiment, three light bulbs were arranged in a row and flashed in succession, forming two spatiotemporal intervals. Participants were asked to compare either the spatial or temporal extents of the two intervals. Often, time judgments were found to increase as a function of the spatial separation between stimuli (the Kappa effect), and distance judgments were found to increase as a function of the temporal separation between stimuli (the Tau effect). At first glance, these experiments appear similar to those w... |
1 |
Mentalese.
- Pinker
- 1994
(Show Context)
Citation Context ...e our own concepts of ‘time,’ ‘space,’ and ‘matter’ given in substantially the same form by experience to all men, or are they in part conditioned by the structure of particular languages?” (1939/2000, pg. 138.) This Whorfian question remains the subject of renewed interest and debate. Does language shape thought? The answer yes would call for a reexamination of the ‘universalist’ assumption that has guided Cognitive Science for decades, according to which nonlinguistic concepts are formed independently of the words that name them, and are invariant across languages and cultures (Fodor, 1975; Pinker, 1994, Papafragou, Massey, & Gleitman, 2002). This position is often attributed to Chomsky (1975), but has been articulated more recently by Pinker (1994) and by Lila Gleitman and colleagues (Papafragou, Massey, & Gleitman, 2002; Snedeker & Gleitman, 2004). The Shallow View proposed here can be considered a variety of the universalist view that can plausibly be maintained despite recent psycholinguistic evidence supporting the Whorfian hypothesis (e.g., Boroditsky, 2001). Skepticism about some Whorfian claims has been well founded (see Pinker, 1994, ch. 3, for a review of evidence against the Whorf... |
1 | Do we think about music in terms of space: metaphoric representation of musical pitch. - Boroditsky - 2003 |